Tuesday, December 4, 2012

Ambivalence of Awe and Angst: The Will to Suffer

*The final is my final essay for the Foundations of Humanistic Psychology course.





          Abstract: There have been many attempts throughout the history of philosophy and psychology to denote the essence of the human condition and what motivates us as human beings to do the things that we do. Nearly all of these sentiments have been orchestrated as a “will-to- (something).” This essay will briefly examine Freud’s “Will to Pleasure”, Freud’s later revision of the pleasure principle (Will to Live), Nietzsche’s “Will to Power”, and Frankl’s “Will to Meaning.” The foundational premise for this essay is that these previous adaptations are valid and significant, yet lacking the encompassing effect which they were postulated to attain. I suggest that we are driven by a will to suffer in pursuit of awe. The tensions between sublimity and malevolence are directly begotten in awe and angst, thus, the human condition is one profoundered by a pursuit of suffering in spite of angst and in pursuit of awe. We live better through agony.

Introduction:
          Humanity is a driven race. We are motivated, passionate, and stubborn. Various psychological and philosophical theories have attempted to explain what precisely drives humans throughout their existence. An early theory, simple enough in its nature, was that humans' motivations lie on a continuum of pleasure-seeking and pain-avoiding behaviors. This theory was later expanded to deeper roots to be restated as a pursuit of life and avoidance of death or cessation of life. A less biological and more existential approach was then developed to state that the human life is one motivated by a desire for power. Moving strictly into the metaphysical realm, a more recent theory supposed that man is propelled by his personal search for meaning. While these theories still hold substantial ground in today's world I disagree with their comprehensiveness. The following is not an objection to the validity of these theories but a supplemental meta-lense from which they can be observed.
          At first glance, from Webster’s Dictionary (Agnes, 2002, p. 42), “awe” is defined as “a mixed feeling of reverence, fear, and wonder.” It has not taken long to find that language has already failed us within this work. While this brief definition is sufficient in most contexts, it leaves a great deal unspoken and unaccounted for. A 2009 Interview with Kirk J. Schneider is much more suiting as he states; “Awe is the adventure that we’re all on. We’re all hurtling through the depths and darkness of space and time... that’s fascinating as well as a little unsettling, but the combination is very powerful because I basically define awe as the humility and wonder, or adventure of living.” What, then, is the importance of wonder and awe? “Wonder doesn’t teach so much as it evokes, and what one senses and stores from such experiences leads to an altogether different experiencing of reality. It moves us to discern the patterns hidden within and behind our society’s accepted vision of reality” (Powell, 2011, p. 132).
          It is from my experience and observation that I suggest human beings are motivated by an eternal struggle, an ambivalent tension, between awe and angst. The foundations of these motivations are what I can only describe in our limited language as sublimity and malevolence. Sublimity and malevolence are begotten to the world by the very nature of human existence. This existence is one that is procured and conditioned by suffering. The tensions of our lives, of our condition, simultaneously tear us apart yet hold us together at the core. We live in a state of ambiguity and friction of which there is no remedy. Suffering is both mitigating and exacerbating. However, we are driven by suffering towards the the nostalgic wonder of awe in spite of anxiety. We live better through agony.

Part One: Love and Will
          “Love and do what you will.” Rollo May quotes St. Augustine in Love and Will (1969, p. 216). This is where the motivations of our human condition begin to take hold. Our condition is a state of loving and doing. This state is closely related to our being (ie: “state of being”). However, what we love and what we do are only the mere expositions of “who” we are. The repository for these expositions is a matter of will. Will, then, is the manner in which our being presents itself to other beings and things. There are a vast number of psychoanalytic assumptions pertaining to the actions' reflection of will. For the purposes of this essay let us say that those claims hold at least some validity and that our will is inevitably expressed, be it consciously, subconsciously, or unconsciously.
          The next point of issue is the question of, “What do we love?” As May and Augustine reference love, the question does not accurately portray the word. As proposed by May, the question is not a matter of willing or doing what we love, but of loving and doing what we will. Doing our will is a simple enough procedure, identifying it is a completely different matter that will be explored throughout this essay. Loving our will is not a matter of willing our love. It is a struggling process of coming to terms with our being. It is a reconciliation between the domains of ourselves. Loving our will is a simultaneously vindicating self-forgiveness and realist humbling of expectations.

Part Two: Will to Pleasure
          The “pleasure principle” has deep roots in western culture and psychology. Its foundations can be derived from as early on as Plato and the ancient Greeks. This pleasure principle was brought into a psychological light by Sigmund Freud who asserted that we are motivated by a pursuit of pleasure and an avoidance of pain. The effects of this principle can be seen in relative validity through the example of reinforcing behaviors. For example, corporal punishment is a means of inflicting physical pain towards the end of negative reinforcement. Wherein a negative additional behavior is the repercussion brought about by a person's initial behavior in an attempt to deter future occurrences of the initial behavior. The converse, then being positive reinforcement, is something rewarding an initial behavior to encourage future occurrences of the initial behavior.
          The primary deficit of this example is that it loses its effectiveness once a person is capable of higher-end cognitive and mental functions. That is to say they become aware of the fact that certain behaviors will elicit certain rewards or punishments. In the case of rewards, a child may cognitively become capable of manipulating the rewarder in an attempt to achieve a disproportionate distribution of rewards. This still lends credence toward the pleasure principle, but its counterpart does not. What is to be said of the person who makes the decision that a certain amount of suffering or pain will be worth the desired end-achievement of a pleasurable behavior? Perhaps I find I am allergic to animal dander, but I love my dog nonetheless. I certainly do not enjoy the effects of my allergic reactions, but nevertheless they do not stop me from pursuing the pleasure I find in my canine companion. “Contrary to loss aversion, predicted pleasure is greater in magnitude than predicted pain, and experienced pleasure surpasses experienced pain” (Mellers, 2009, p. 369).
          On a different tier there is a problem with the intrinsic provocations of the pleasure principle. It has become far too common for people to mistake pleasure for happiness and satisfaction. The examples of this are numerous, the wealthy stockbroker on Fifth Avenue who commits suicide, the teenager who presumes satisfaction in listless sexual promiscuity, or even in a technological realm where the latest application for my smartphone is pleasurable in its own right but has little lasting effect on how existentially satisfying I find my life to be. It should be noted that happiness and pleasure may be satisfying, but they are not always so. If taken in appropriate context of our will and our being, satisfaction implies fulfilled happiness without complete regard to, but unregulated by, pleasure and pain.
          In a similar vein, pain does not always equal unhappiness or dissatisfaction. The pet example above is one admission to this case. Another would be a hearty morning stretch. Literally, albeit in a very moderate sense, you are making your body do something unnatural, pull itself apart. Nevertheless, stretching is often relaxing and pleasurable. This is especially true in the context of yoga (for example). Dissatisfaction encompasses unhappiness and that unhappiness can sometimes result from something painful. Dissatisfaction itself may even be found to be painful. But the painful is not always the source of the dissatisfying unhappiness.

Part Three: Will to Live
          The Pleasure Principle was later revised in Freud’s work Beyond the Pleasure Principle. Pleasure and pain are thus revised to libido / eros and thanatos (ie: life and death). Libido and eros vs. thanatos equate to desire vs. destructiveness (Arundale, 2006, p. 454). This destructiveness is also known as the Death Drive, of which the aim is “the originary state of matter, a state where all forces are drawn into a final leveling out” (Lapanche, 2004, p. 460). Libido, on the other hand, is a drive to experience, love, learn, and grow (Arundale, 2006, p. 453).
          In this representation of will, we are failed by their linear dimensions. Consider, for example, that the opposite of love is not hate. Love and hate are merely two sides of the same coin, masks on the same face. The opposite of both love and hate is apathy. Love and hate are often considered opposing forces, however, this is only true when the constraints of the scale which they are measured on are limited by context. Here we find the intrinsic problem of this argument. Libido and Thanatos are not opposites. How little would we learn or love of life if we were not brought to terms with the harsh reality of just how fragile and destructible life is. “... as a result of this mass anesthesia, or you could almost say hypnosis, we lose not only the uncomfortable part of us but it blocks out our capacity to become exhilarated, to experience and express great joy... We have fewer and fewer places that help us cultivate that. We’ve become atrophied in terms of our ability to experience the ranges of our thoughts and feelings about our life” (Schneider, 2009). If the Death Drive is, in fact, the totaling of everything into a homeostatic void then its opposite would be every conceivable sensation running full throttle at its red-line. Mellers (2009, p. 369) states that “people value giving up a good more than they value getting it.” This, in turn, makes the case that we are more concerned with avoiding death than we are pursuing life. However, as far as I am concerned, living is merely a biological process, being alive, rather, is a matter of idio-hermeneutic-phenomenology. “Life comes from physical survival; but the good life comes from what we care about” (May, 1969, p. 290).

Part Four: Will to Power
          The next consideration is Nietzsche’s “Will to Power.” The Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy states that “Will to power is the fundamental character of life and the world... life is will to power, and thus degree of power constitutes the standard of value” (Leiter, 2004). This brings a new element into the discussion and that is “value.” Value is something mentioned earlier in the discussion of pleasure and pain with regards to satisfaction. Here we are getting closer to the source of our desires and furthermore our will. What we desire is control. We desire power over our will so that we can manipulate the will to our defined satisfaction rather than molding our satisfaction to the will. Perhaps Nietzsche is onto something here. We may desire pleasure or life, maybe even pain and death, but it is only because of the power we hold over the attributed value of those things.
          I fear that the efforts of this form of will are indeed in vain. We are chasing an impossible feat. Our desire invokes our will and the will evokes desire. That is, the desire is a function of our will and thus will remains the primary and desire the subordinate. Nevertheless our desire is how our will shows itself to our outward world and to our conscious mind. Nietzsche leaves us pleading for an unattainable control of the untamed will. Yet we will onward, but to what end and with what value?

Part Five: Will to Meaning
          “Man’s search for meaning is the primary motivation in his life and not a ‘secondary realization’ of instinctual drives. This meaning is unique and specific in that it must and can be fulfilled by him alone; only then does it achieve a significance which will satisfy his own will to meaning” (Frankl, 1984, p. 105). Frankl illustrates some very important concepts here. Firstly, there are what he is calling instinctual drives. Drives such as death and pleasure have been historically analyzed and acclaimed causal in retrospect. Thus, any attributed will or motivation is merely an a posteriori relationship rather than an a priori cause. Secondly, what can be said about the fulfillment of meaning and power? Power is a self-gratifying meaning. It presupposes that control is gratifying because we then have the capability and resources to exude an unadulterated will and quasi-personal value to that which we dub “meaningful.”
          Frankl is off to a good start in his argument. Pleasure, pain, life, death, and power have meanings which are attributed momentary insurmountable significance through hermeneutical observations of phenomenological existences. Unfortunately Frankl betrays himself in the above statement, revealing that we are ultimately striving for satisfaction. Frankl presumes that a fulfilled meaning will be satisfactory. Out of sheer stubbornness I am forced to ask; “What if I am satisfied in my contention in meaninglessness?”
          Frankl also writes that “What matters, therefore, is not the meaning of life in general but rather the specific meaning of a person’s life at a given moment” (1984, p. 113). But momentary satisfaction is just that; temporary, passing, and ultimately insignificant. Constant analysis and meaning seeking becomes a neurotic compulsion for the existential. This compulsion to attribute meaning is riddled with angst and underlying, constantly itching, desire for ease. This is followed by a subliminal motive for peace of mind which propagates a willingness towards stimulation. Thus the cycle continues, without end, and in loathing scorn of fateful value. Yet man is always searching for something; shelter, food and water, safety and security, social relationships, power, meaning, etc... We will constantly be reminded of our dissatisfaction once the moment of attributed meaning passes into a nuance of re-imagined meaninglessness.

Part Six: Will to Suffer
          I do not presume to be more right than any of the other theorists previously described. However, I feel that their statements are lacking. They have become isolated and fed the products of their own factories. They have become narrowly constrained to the vision they project on the world. I propose that there is a sense of wonder beyond any of the previously stated concepts. There is a something that has been missed, ignored, or intentionally omitted by the previous theorists. We are, in fact, motivated by an ambivalent tension between sublimity and malevolence. The conflicting feelings create an existential friction which, in succumbing to its own captivation, propels us onward.
          The importance of this tension between sublimity and malevolence is that the two are irreconcilable. They can not become equalitative. They cannot reach a compromising equilibrium. Equilibrium is a state in which something integral is lost from the individual sides. By definition, a compromise suggests Party A giving up something in exchange for an offering from Party B. In this trade both parties confidently hope that the exchange received will be of more satisfying value than the projected loss they are giving up. Equilibrium is boredom. Boredom gives fertility to angst and existential dismay. “The existential vacuum manifests itself in a state of boredom” (Frankl, 1984, p. 111).
          Furthermore, what we are avoiding is not pain or death, but angst. In terms of death, what can be said of one in which I would be satisfied? What if I am satisfied with my life (inclusive of its pain, pleasure, power, meaning, or meaninglessness) and thus not merely content with, but satisfied in my dying? Angst is a feeling of anxiety, apprehension, or insecurity thus encompassing the avoidance drives and motivations previously mentioned. There is something tragic about paradise, tragic to the human condition. This condition is one that is in agony yet revels in the presence of its being no matter how it is procured.
          Suffering is part of humanity. To presume our perfect state of being would be one of pure joy is quite pretentious of our vainglorious ego. Perhaps we fear suffering. I must disagree. I suggest we fear undirected and task-less suffering; which is descriptive of angst. One may ask, “Why, then, are we not motivated by an avoidance of fear?” Fear’s ultimate end is crippling catatonic paranoia. Fear is the tool of angst, not its commander. The lack of fear is ignorance which plants the seeds of anxiety in the fields of boredom.
          Our motivations therefore lie in the pursuit of awe. It is such because in awe “you are able to occupy parts of your being that you wouldn’t have even thought about before, especially if you’re world hadn’t been shaken. And through reoccupying those places you have greater access to the ranges of your feelings, thoughts, sensations, intuitions. You’re really more open in a lot of ways if you can work with that turmoil” (Schneider, 2009). Consider the terms “awesome” and “awful.” The two are typically thought of as antonymous. Yet both can be defined as “inspiring awe” (Agnes, 2002, p. 42). The second entries under each respective word in Webster's New World Dictionary are “wonderful” and “terrifying” (Agnes, 2002, p. 42). The clear root of both “awesome” and “awful” is “awe.” From which we can only assume that awe is something that is strikingly wonderful and terrifying. Thus we see that the vehicle towards awe is a world shaken by turmoil, perfectly efficient its utter suffering.
          Earlier I stated that awe and angst are the manifestations of malevolence and awe. Let me first make clear why this essay is not directed at a will to sublimity or avoidance of malevolence. This relationship is similar to that of will and desire. Our will is the part of our being which can be used to look but can never be seen. It is the unspoken voice which is always heard. Our desire is the mechanism that associates value to the message of our will. Malevolence and sublimity are unshakable, predominate, primordial forces instilled in us and brought to prospective by awe and angst.
Malevolence can be defined as wishing evil or harm to another (Agnes, 2002, p. 385). However, this should be expanded to include the intra-personal realm. Angst, thus being, the ultimate self-malevolent provocation. Malevolence, then, manifests itself in angst and is evoked towards others and the self as a defense mechanism of our will voraciously asserting a dissatisfaction with the self. Sublimity, on the other hand, is manifested in awe. Awe is an encompassing fruition of our maximum emotional, cognitive, and metaphysical capacity to feel, to mean, and to experience all that this life has to offer; all in a single unforgeable experience. “We are simultaneously worms and gods” (Maslow, 2009, p. 72).
As mentioned before, the relationships between pain-pleasure, power-powerlessness, and meaning-meaninglessness are severely limited in their ascriptive ability because of their linear scale. This scale is merely a one-dimensional continuum which implies that one end of the spectrum is dependent on the other (or at least a deficit of the other). The relationship between awe and angst is not causal. This relationship breaks the dimensions into an altogether different spectrum. A second dimension of intensity does nothing to improve the scale. Even a third dimension does not do the relationship justice, but it does help illustrate the point. The spectrum of awe and angst is one in which we relate to ourselves, our past, other people, and other objects.
Awe is not the opposite of angst, nor is that the rationale of this argument. Rather, awe is inclusive of angst. We become awe-depleted when we begin to limit this spectrum. When we focus too intensely on any one of the dimension of this spectrum we become neurotic which, at least in a temporary sense, is inevitable. Neurosis may be inevitable but it need not be permanent. When neurosis becomes our defining characteristic, when we become locked too deeply within or outside ourselves, we give a lasting foothold to angst. Our deepest avoidance drive is suffering without meaning, a state in which our being has succumbed to a nihilistic agony and a crippling, suffocating anxiety. “Awe based consciousness embraces both anxiety and possibilities of living” (Schneider, 2009). Awe embraces the suffering, the anxiety, and the agony as well as the ecstasy, the prowess, the satisfaction, and the beauty of life.

Part Seven: Will to Awe
          We have an innate will to awe which is achieved along a highway wrought with suffering. When our focus remains on suffering merely for the sake of suffering we are driven towards neurotic angst. Embracing suffering, not merely acknowledging it, as an invaluable part of our existent being leads to the full embodiment of our human condition which leaves us, thus, in awe. We continue forward with an uncertain end and certainly no foreseeable end to our suffering. We continue nevertheless. We continue to suffer in spite of angst, in revolt against it, in light of awe and wonder. Awe is the wonder and appreciation of the majesty of life’s absurdly fateful suffering. “Once wonder is experienced it can be sought because we rightly believe it is attainable... in the thrall of wonder we do not feel alone and our world has new patterns seen bubbling up within it” (Powell, 2011, p. 132).
          We could not possibly be who we are today without having been who we were yesterday. Concurrently, we could not have achieved all that we value and find satisfying without having suffered through the past. We would be completely devoid of any existential satisfaction in the joys of our life if they had not been “earned” through suffering. That is not to say that one must suffer, but that s/he wills it. Suffering adds an ineffable quality to our state of being. Simply put, we appreciate things to a much more intrinsic extent when they do not come easily to us.
          Frankl (1984, p. 106) writes that “pseudo values” have to be unmasked. Pleasure, power, meaning, pain, weakness, and void are all masks worn by desire to deceive and distract us. When the masks, some even approaching awe on their own, are stripped away we are left in utter wonder of what lies behind the veil. We are left, staring our will and our fate in the eyes. We are glaring at the very core of our being, what has truly been there all along. When all the pollution of our lives and ourselves is reduced to its complete raw and authentic state, all that remains is awe. There is everything and there is nothing, yet the beauty of the human condition rages brilliantly nonetheless. Awe has never ceased to be present. Though diluted and anesthetized by our desire, our will has never been more clear. “We must continue to struggle” (Maslow, 2009, p. 138).


Works Cited
Agnes, M., & Laird, C. (2002). ambivalence, awe, awesome, awful, benevolent, fear, malevolent, sublime. In Webster's New World Dictionary and Thesaurus (2nd ed., pp. 19-631). angst. (2012). In Merriam-Webster. Retrieved November 27, 2012, from http://www.merriam-webster.com/dictionary/angst
Arundale, J. (2004). Eros and Thanatos in Context. British Journal Of Psychotherapy,
20(4), 453-454. doi:10.1111/j.1752-0118.2004.tb00163.x
Frankl, V. E. (1984). Man's Search for Meaning (3rd ed., pp. 103-136). New York, NY:
Simon & Schuster.
Laplanche, J. (2004). The So-Called 'Death Drive': A Sexual Drive.British Journal Of
Psychotherapy, 20(4), 455-471. doi:10.1111/j.1752-0118.2004.tb00164.x
Leiter, B. (2004). Nietzsche's Moral and Political Philosophy. In E. N. Zalta (Ed.),
Stanford Encyclopedia of Philosophy (Summer 2011 ed.). Retrieved November
Maslow, A. (1999). Toward a Psychology of Being (3rd ed., pp. 72-138). New York, NY:
John Wiley & Sons.
May, R. (1969). Love and Will (pp. 216-290). New York, NY: W. W. Norton & Company.
Mellers, B. A., & Ritov, I. (2009, August 4). How Beliefs Influence the Relative
Magnitude of Pleasure and Pain. Journal of Behavioral Decision Making, 23,
369-382. doi:10.1002/bdm.662
Powell, W. E. (2011). Wonder Happens and Then We Come Alive. Families in Society,
92(2), 131-132. doi:10.1606/1044-3894.4112
Schneider, Kirk J. Interview by Michael Toms. "Awakening to Awe." New Dimensions
Radio. Nov. 2009. Web. 30 Oct. 2012. <http://www.kirkjschneider.com/media.html>.

No comments:

Post a Comment